Legal positivism is one of the most influential school of thought in
jurisprudence which developed in the West, especially Britain. Their basic aim
is to understand law as it actually is and how it is found in actual practices
or in the institution of society. Positivists regard law as a ‘social fact’ and
separate it from morals. In other words, we can say positivists are not
concerned how law is ‘ought to be’ but how it is in practice.
Though, most laws
are based on morals, positivist say that there should be no necessary relation
or connection between morals and laws. A moral rule is a rule because of its
content. In contrast, the legal rule is legal not owing to its content but only
because it has been constituted in a particular fashion, born of definite
procedure and definite rule of law. Conversely, a morally repugnant rule will be
a law if it has been made according to the established procedure or the criteria
for validity.[1]
Some positivist consider that a law to be called a law must
emanate from or must be recognized by an established authority, whereas some
consider customary rules which are followed from ages as laws as well. However,
they create a distinction between these customary laws and the laws developed by
the given legal system. It also states that laws are the creation of human and
does not flow from some divine entity. Thus, we can say that positivist
undertake an empirical perspective of looking at laws by leaving behind
subjectivities related with morals.
Cultural pluralism is one the main features of Indian society. India is home to
different races, religious groups, tribes etc and each of these groups have
their unique characteristics. In such a context, legal pluralism plays an
relevant role in India by putting law above the various customs and traditions
that are at times contradictory to one another. In this research work, the
researcher discusses the basic characteristics of pluralism and attempts to find
the relevance of positivism in culturally plural Indian society.
What Is Positivism?
Legal positivism is one of the most influential school of thought in
jurisprudence. The start of the nineteenth century might be taken as marking the
beginning of the positivist movement. Legal positivism at birth was part of the
wider 18th century intellectual movement known as the enlightenment, which
turned away traditions, superstitions and irrationality to embrace empiricism
and science.[2] It was developed largely by Jeremy Bentham and John Austin and
was subsequently taken forward by eminent jurist such as H.L.A Hart and Joseph
Raz. The above jurists have significant differences in their views but the
common idea that all of the above jurists have is that they analyze law as it
is.[3]
There is division among different positivist based on the weightage they give to
morals. The division is between soft positive positivist and negative
positivist. Positivist such as Hart are regarded as positive positivist or ‘soft
positivist’ as they give recognition to moral principles whereas positivist like
Austin are negative positivist as they completely negate the existence of moral
principles. Therefore, legal positivism doesn’t completely negate the existence
of morality by rather attempts to separate law and morality.
The term positivism has different meanings, which were tabulated by professor
Hart as follows:
(1) Law are commands. This meaning is associated with the founders of positivism
Bentham and his disciple Austin.
(2) The analysis of legal concept is:
(a) worth pursuing,
(b) free from sociological and historical enquiries,
(c) distinct from critical evaluation.
(3) Decision can be deduced logically from pre-determined rules without recourse
to social aims, policy or morality.
(4) Moral judgment cannot be established or defended by rational arguments,
evidence or proof.
(5) The law as it is actually laid down, positum, has to be kept separate from
the law that ought to be.[4] It is the first meaning given by Hart that is
presently associated with positivism. It may spring from love to order, which
aims at the clarification of legal conception and their orderly presentation.[5]
Legal positivism is the child of utilitarian moral theory and strives to advance
the public good. The main contention is that law can be made better if it is not
confused with morality. Their main objective it to make people understand law
‘as it is’ and not as law ‘ought to be’. The common theme among all the jurist
from school of legal positivism is to create clear distinction between law and
moral principles as well as legal duty and moral duty. The legal positivist
propound that there is no relation between law and morality. However, they were
of the view that law might reflect the morality of the person or body who
controls it; and therefore there was no necessary connection between law and
morality but is what is laid down by the superior authority.
Relevance of Positivism In Culturally Plural Indian Society
The Merriam Webster dictionary defines pluralism or cultural pluralism as: ‘a
situation in which people of different social classes, religion, races, etc.,
are together in a society but continue to have their different traditions and
interest.’ It refers to a situation where multiple smaller groups within a
larger society have distinct cultural identities. In a culturally plural
society, there is the existence of a dominant culture, unlike in
multiculturalism, where there is no dominant culture.
Every civilization has certain unique characteristics or features of its own.
India is distinct from other civilizations of the world in respect to its
continuity and heterogeneity. India is the host of different cultural groups.
Since the middle of the second millennium BC, Indian civilization has played
host to several streams of migrant groups and communities from different parts
of the world. The advent of the Aryans, the Tibeto-Burman speaking Mongoloid
groups, the Kushans, the Sakas, the Greeks, the Huns, the Arabs, the Persians,
the Turks and the Mongols at different points of time testifies to the
pervasiveness of the migration process during the successive periods of Indian
history. The migrant groups and communities brought their respective traditions
and behaviour patterns from their native lands. In the course of time they lost
contact with their places of origin and underwent an extensive process of
indigenization. The process of adaptation and interaction among the various
groups brought about, on the one hand, India’s characteristic diversity and, on
the other, a composite cultural tradition.[6]
In a culturally plural society, the separation of law and morality becomes even
more essential. Morality is a subjective term and differs from one culture to
another, i.e. what maybe moral for one cultural community may not be so for the
other. It is not possible for the state or the sovereign to concede with the
meaning of morality of all the groups in a culturally plural society and
conceding with only one form of morality will go against the others. The same
applies for culturally plural India. Positivism is characterized as making clear
distinction between law and morality. According to Austin and Bentham law and
morality are completely different entities, and Hart holds that law and morality
need not have any necessary connection. This character of positivism becomes
relevant in India, as for different groups ‘what ought to be law’ differs,
therefore, with positivism the law which is established is accepted as it is
without any moral qualification. Positive law is the product of empiricism and
scientific thinking and takes a stand free from morality. The law, by
authoritatively stating the rule to follow, relieves people of the interminable
discussion about right conduct.[7] However, a law maybe against the interest of
certain sections. To this, we can apply Hartian perspective of law to this
problem. Hart states that law requires minimum content of natural law. A legal
system that is effective may produce laws that many consider to be morally
repugnant. Yet it will be valid laws if they if they satisfy the criteria set by
the rule of recognition.[8] Hart saw many ways in which law and morality can be
linked. But these were, for Hart, not necessary but contingent connections.[9]
Morality constantly influences law making by legislators and judges. In some
countries the constitution lays down moral teat in form of fundamental rights
and freedoms that every law must pass in order to be valid. This test, hart and
other positivist argue, are enforceable not because of their morality but
because they constitute an established rule of recognition.[10]
Norberto Bobbio has singled out three main conceptions of legal positivism:
methodological positivism, theoretical positivism, ideological positivism.[11]
Methodological†positivism is a peculiar way to conceive of the function of
legal knowledge and, at the same time, of the object of legal knowledge itself.
The legal positivist is characterized by commitment to a value-free, scientiï¬c
approach in studying actual law. From this important methodological tenet it
thus follows that there is a sharp distinction between “actual†law and “idealâ€
or “natural†law: between law as a fact and law as a value; a distinction which
aims to point to the former as the proper (indeed only) object of legal
knowledge.[12] In a culturally plural society, every section has different
interests, which maybe contradictory to each other. Therefore, it is essential
for the legal authority to be value neutral.
Bentham laid down the utilitarian principle which states that law should create
‘greatest happiness of the greatest number’, thus positivism in a culturally
plural society ensures that the interest if the maximum population is served
rather than taking moral stand based on interest of one community over other.
A culturally plural society has different groups with its own religion and
practices. In addition, each of this religion comes with a set of laws. If each
of these groups were to prescribe to their religious laws, each of the groups
will come into contradiction with the other. The will of the sovereign as stated
by Bentham and Austin is the law in actual and it would avoid such
contradictions. Furthermore, it would be a serious problem for a theory of law
that it made the nature of law dependent on the will of God, since we have
neither good reason to think God exists (and much reason to think he does not),
nor reliable epistemic access to his will (if he did exist). It is a virtue of
legal positivism that its picture of the world is metaphysically austere: it
requires only persons and their psychological states to explain the social
phenomenon of law. Theoretical virtue of legal positivism is that it has no need
for such an ontology.[13]
In a culturally plural society like India, there are many customs and practices
practice of which may hamper another section. Therefore following law from one
single source will prevent conflict. According to Hans Kelson, the constitution
of a nation represents the ‘basic norm’ of the nation and the only legitimate
source of law. It is the constitution on which the law of the land is based upon
and everyone must act in accordance to it.
The above discussion showing relevance of ‘Legal positivism’ in culturally
plural India society can be elaborated by the case: Suresh Kachhadia v. Union of
India
In this case, Mr. Kachhadia had filed a PIL seeking direction to Central and
State government to make it mandatory for manufacturers to print details of
goods like price, ingredients and date of manufacture in Hindi, contending that
it should be done so as hindi is the national language. He contended it on the
basis that Hindi is the national language as it is understood and spoken by a
large number of people.
The Gujarat High Court has observed in this case that though majority of people
in India spoke Hindi and considered it as the national language but there was
nothing on record to establish the position of Hindi as the national language.
The observation made by S.J Mukhopadhaya C.J, and A.S Dave J. observed that
“Normally, in India, majority of the people have accepted Hindi as a national
language and many people speak Hindi and write in Devanagari script but there is
nothing on record to suggest that any provision has been made or order issued
declaring Hindi as a national language of the country.â€[14] The court further
exalted that “no mandamus can be issued on any manufacturer or others for giving
details or particulars of package in Hindi in Devnagari script.â€[15]
The court took this position the basis that Hindi was declared as an official
language and not a national language.[16] The court in its order said Part XVII
of the Constitution deals with Official Language. Under Art.343, official
language of the Union has been prescribed, which includes Hindi in Devnagari
script and English.[17]
This case acts as an example that shows the separation of law from morality and
in this case the interest of the majority and decides the case on basis. In this
case, Constitution of India or the basic norm of India was upheld over the
majority view, opinion or interest. The court decided on the basis of what is
laid down in the constitution, i.e., Art. 343. Positivism is based on scientism
and social facts and the court in this case took account of the lingual
diversity in India. Looking at the case from the Austinian sense, the law of
sovereign is the ultimate law and the court as the delegate of the sovereign
held that the Hindi is not the national language of India.
This given case shows the relevance of positivism in culturally plural society.
Law devoid of moral consideration and ‘as it is’ ensures uniformity and prevent
cumbersome problems that may arise while taking into consideration morality
represented by one group while ignoring the other.
Conclusion
Positivism or legal pluralism is a school of thought that see law ‘as it is’ and
not as it ‘ought to be’. It is based on empirical and scientific outlook on
social facts. Positivism doesn’t consider the source of law to be some unknown
transcendental authority but rather the will of the sovereign. The main
objective of positivists is to make a clear distinction between law and
morality.
India is a culturally plural society with diversity in race, language, food
habits, religion, lifestyle etc. Indian society is characterized with the
existence of different groups with distinct identities. Positivism in culturally
plural society prevents conflict between cultural or religious rules of
different groups by putting the law of the sovereign and the constitution above
all. It maintains value neutrality and thus ensures the benefits of the greater
number are taken into account rather than a particular section of the society.
Positivism separates law and morality. Though, at times law and morality maybe
connected but such connection is not necessary. Positive law by not prescribing
to some eternal law but rather to the will of the sovereign ensure uniformity of
law as well as a proper singular source of law. Positivism from Kelsen’s
perspective makes the Constitution the ‘basic norm’ or ‘grundnorm’, i.e., the
sole legitimate source from which all rules and laws follows and the case and
conflicts are resolved on the basis of the Constitution and thus the question of
discrimination of the interest of one section and exclusion of the other does
not arise.
End-Notes
[1] Suri Ratnapala, Jurisprudence, Cambridge University Press India Pvt. Ltd.,
Delhi, 2009
[2] Suri Ratnapala, Jurisprudence, Cambridge University Press India Pvt. Ltd.,
Delhi, 2009
[3] H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law, Clarendon Law Series, 1961
[4] R.W.M Dias, Jurisprudence, Lexis Nexis, Haryana, 2013
[5] R.W.M Dias, Jurisprudence, Lexis Nexis, Haryana, 2013
[6] http://ignca.nic.in/ls_03016.htm, accessed on 27th October, 2015
[7] Suri Ratnapala, Jurisprudence, Cambridge University Press India Pvt. Ltd.,
Delhi, 2009
[8] Ibid
[9] Ibid
[10] Ibid
[11] GIORGIO PINO, THE PLACE OF LEGAL POSITIVISM IN CONTEMPORARY CONSTITUTIONAL
STATES, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Netherlands, February 28, 1999
[12] Ibid
[13] http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1386&context=public_law_and_legal_theory,
accessed on 27th October, 2015
[14] Suresh Bhai Kachhadia v. Union of India, 2010 SCC OnLine Guj 187
[15] Ibid
[16] http://factsfootprint.blogspot.in/2012/09/real-foot-print-of-fact-hindi-not.html,
accessed on 27th October, 2015
[17] Ibid
Please Drop Your Comments